[EL] Check out Study shows who breaks campaign laws - The Pueblo Chieftai...
BZall at aol.com
BZall at aol.com
Wed Aug 10 11:42:02 PDT 2011
What if one sees the effect of one's past actions (in this case, creating a
regulatory scheme which has the effect of causing hardship to those
without the means to hire capable counsel), decries that effect, and then does
the same thing again?
Like the ABA Administrative Law Section, which got the ABA to enact a
resolution to create a lobbying regulatory agency similar to the FEC, despite
having been told by the ABA Tax Section and its Exempt Organization
Committee's Political Subcommittee that the result will be the same as creating the
FEC?
_http://www.abanow.org/wordpress/wp-content/files_flutter/1312830542104bREV.
pdf_
(http://www.abanow.org/wordpress/wp-content/files_flutter/1312830542104bREV.pdf)
It's hard enough to encourage small exempt organizations to exercise their
legitimate rights to speak truth to power, to assemble to be heard, and to
petition the government for redress of grievances in light of incredibly
complicated IRS rules differentiating issue advocacy from electioneering
(see, e.g., Rev. Rul 2004-6, with 14 factors to consider). If this proposal
is put in place, there likely will be even more rules than there are now
under the IRC and the LDA. Does anyone seriously think that a new regulatory
agency will REDUCE complexity?
There are, arguably, many possible purposes and many possible consequences
of such a proposal, but clearly there was foreknowledge that at least one
might be the creation of a barrier to the rights of association and
petition. At what point does "purpose" get inferred from prior warning?
Barnaby Zall
Of Counsel
Weinberg, Jacobs & Tolani, LLP
11300 Rockville Pike, Suite 1200
Rockville, MD 20852
301-231-6943 (direct dial)
_www.wjlaw.com_ (http://www.wj/)
bzall at aol.com
_____________________________________________________________
U.S. Treasury Circular 230 Notice
Any U.S. federal tax advice included in this communication (including
any attachments) was not intended or written to be used, and cannot be
used, for the purpose of (i) avoiding U.S. federal tax-related penalties
or (ii) promoting, marketing or recommending to another party any
tax-related matter addressed herein.
_____________________________________________________________
Confidentiality
The information contained in this communication may be confidential, is
intended only for the use of the recipient named above, and may be legally
privileged. It is not intended as legal advice, and may not be relied upon
or used as legal advice. Nor does this communication establish an attorney
client relationship between us. If the reader of this message is not the
intended recipient, you are hereby notified that any dissemination,
distribution, or copying of this communication, or any of its contents, is
strictly prohibited. If you have received this communication in error,
please re-send this communication to the sender and delete the original
message and any copy of it from your computer system. Thank you.
______________________________________________________________
In a message dated 8/10/2011 2:13:50 P.M. Eastern Daylight Time,
VOLOKH at law.ucla.edu writes:
Let me offer a friendly amendment: One can indeed assume (as a factual
matter) that people intend – in the sense of purposefully aim at – the
natural and probable consequences of their acts, but only if there are no other
natural and probable consequences of note. Thus, even in criminal law, if
I point a loaded gun at someone and pull the trigger, a jury is entitled
(though not required) to infer that I intended to kill the person, or at
least seriously wound him, since that’s the main significant consequence of my
action – though even there one could imagine circumstances that would rebut
the inference.
But such an inference stops being sensible when an action has many natural
and probable consequences. There, as Brian points out, one could act with
the purpose of creating one consequence, and in spite of (i.e., without the
purpose of creating) another consequence. Thus, to consider a crime that
famously turns on purpose – treason – say that I organize a strike during
wartime, knowing that it will foreseeably interfere with the war effort and
help the enemy. That might be treason if I’m doing it with the purpose
of helping the enemy, but it’s not if I’m doing with the purpose of getting
better wages for members of my union, even if I know that it likely will
help the enemy. Nor would it be sound for a jury to infer a purpose to help
the enemy simply because that is a natural and probable consequence of my
actions: Because there are two natural and probable consequences (raising
wages, and helping the enemy), the mere act does not tell us what its
purpose likely was.
Eugene
-------------- next part --------------
An HTML attachment was scrubbed...
URL: <http://webshare.law.ucla.edu/Listservs/law-election/attachments/20110810/811cfa40/attachment.html>
View list directory