This post responds to comments by Bob Bauer and Dan Lowenstein on Bush
v. Gore and the use of murky (or "judicially unmanageable") standards.
Here is what Bob wrote most recently:
Fair enough: but if the Court in Bush v. Gore did what it should not
have done--create a new standard unmoored in social consensus--why not
cordon off the decision rather than encourage its extension by lower
courts? In fact, the Court actively promoted a limited reading: why
would its critics, yourself included, aggressively seek a more expansive
one--or at least a potentially more expansive one flowing from lower
court experimentation? Why not end the mischief at its source? The
answer for some is, that the case proves irresistibly useful to
achieving certain results. Hence a case criticized as an episode in
brazen result orientation becomes the basis for still more of the same.
I do not see how that makes sense--much less promotes respect for law,
or for the proper boundaries for judicial intervention in democratic life.
***
Dan wrote:
A small question for Rick. Why do you include Reynolds v. Sims as a
case that set murky standards? The one person, one vote rule seems
pretty clear to me. Indeed, as I have argued elsewhere, pluralist
critics of Reynolds were wrong to criticize Reynolds as an impediment to
group-based political competition. Reynolds was a one-time shock that
might be thought of as moving where the ball was on the field, but it
left the competition to go on largely as before. It was Stewart's
supposedly more restrained insistence on rationality that invited
continuous judicial intervention into districting.
***
Let me respond to Dan's question first, because it will help answer
Bob's questions too. My list of cases (Reynolds, Shaw, Bush v. Gore)
was not a list of cases in which I said the court DID set murky
standards. It was a list of cases where, if the court was going to
create a new equal protection standard out of whole cloth, it SHOULD use
murky standards.
My work criticizes Reynolds precisely for not moving slowly through the
political thicket by examining various ways of implementing more
equipopulous voting standards. I think the country would have benefited
from a period in which Stewart's exceptionally mushy standard had been
put in place. Then lower courts could have taken various strategies in
trying to operationalize the new standard, and the court would have much
more information, and a better menu to choose from, in crafting either a
strict or a more flexible one person, one vote rule.
Had the Court done so, I argue, we would not have ended up with cases
like Avery, applying one person, one vote on the local level, thereby
(as Richard Briffault and Bruce Cain have ably shown) thwarted the
ability to form effective regional governments.
This is not to say that the Court in Reynolds, Shaw, and Bush v. Gore
was RIGHT to create the new equal protection standard. That is a
difficult question, and one that I tackle in another chapter with
reference primarily to social consensus but also to a core of certain
political equality rights that do not depend upon social consensus. But
once the Court, for good or for ill, goes down the road of creating a
new contested political equality right, it should do so with murky
standards.
The appropriate role for the lower courts (and now this is more directly
responsive to Bob) is to try out the new standard in various ways,
bringing in policy and facts in particular factual contexts that would
not necessarily have been apparent to the Supreme Court at the time it
creates the new right. After a period of lower court experimentation,
the Court can then judge how best to operationalize the new right.
I should note that I do NOT believe the Court in cases like Bush or Shaw
PURPOSELY chose a murky standard for these reasons. But I do believe
the murky standards in such cases can serve salutary purposes.