Subject: Re: McConnell v. FEC: The big picture |
From: Bruce Cain |
Date: 12/14/2003, 1:11 PM |
To: marty.lederman@comcast.net |
CC: "Bauer, Bob-WDC" <RBauer@perkinscoie.com>, "''Rick Hasen ' '" <Rick.Hasen@lls.edu>, election-law@majordomo.lls.edu |
in reply to marty, Again, not to take anything away from marty's insights on the case per se, I just want to caution against loose assertions about what we obviously know and do not know. Marty gives perfectly plausible reasons to support his conjecture that soft money thru the parties is more corrupting than indendent spending etc., but l can give perfectly plausible arguments on the other side. Often evidence simply does not support plausible conjectures. I am well aware that the Court had other reasons for treating personal and independent spending differently from contributions, but this unproven emprirical assertion was and still is critical to their different treatment of various elements of campaign finance reform. We are at the start of our first campaign cycle under BCRA. I have not noticed that trade union and coporate influence has diminished. I will keep looking. I have not noticed that bills coming thru Congress are any less shaped by shaped by special interests. But maybe it is just too early...we will see. More likely old influences will simply follow new paths. Bruce Cain On Sun, 14 Dec 2003 marty.lederman@comcast.net wrote:
On these sorts of empirical questions, my guesses no doubt are no better than anyone else's, and probably a whole lot less informed than those of many on this list. But here's one response: Do I think that the "corrupting connection" of soft money through the parties is greater than the "corrupting connection" that results from the independent expenditures of PACs, unincorporated 527s, wealthy individuals, etc.? Well, my gut tells me "yes," for reasons that include the following: (i) parties can spend much higher amounts of $$ on contributions to candidates; (ii) parties can and do make much greater coordinated expenditures with candidates; (iii) candidates may not control, or even suggest by a "wink" or "nod," what the nonparties' independent expenditures should be; (iv) parties' principal reason for being is to elect the candidates that they've nominated, whereas nonparties typically have much broader and more diverse interests and agendas; (v) officeholders and candidates have central roles within the parties; (vi) parties are uniquely situated to provide contributors with access to officeholders; etc. All of which is to say that if I were a candidate, I!
imagine a contribution by X to my party of $Y would be much more valuable to me than an independent expenditure by X of $Y, or than a contribution by X of $Y to a 527 or a PAC. That appears to be Congress's assumption -- and the Court's -- as well. (Indeed, IIRC, it is precisely for these sorts of reasons that the parties themselves have argued, in cases such as Colorado Republicans I and II, that party committees should have greater constitutional rights than nonparty PACs.)
Now, none of this is to say that candidates (and, more importantly, officeholders) do not feel beholden, to some degree, to folks who make independent expenditures on their behalf, or who make contributions to 527s and PACs that are, in turn, used to subsidize such independent expenditures. Of course they do, even if not to the same extent as when that same money is given to the candidate herself (or to her party). I don't think that the Court has said otherwise, or has "overridden" any 1973 congressional judgment in this respect. The Court in Buckley merely concluded (i) that such independent expenditures presumptively do not result in the *same degree* of corruption as do contributions to candidates (and their parties), for many of the reasons stated above; and, more importantly, (ii) expenditure limitations (unlike contribution limitations) are subject to strict scrutiny, which requires a much *greater* showing of corruption in order to justify such a limitation, and!
which involves *far* less deference to congressional judgments. (I know this is a rough summary, but I think the basics are accurate.) As far as I know, although the Court has sustained virtually every contribution limitation that it has reviewed on a "corruption" rationale, it has sustained *no* expenditure limitations on such a rationale. (In Austin, Justice Stevens would have upheld the corporate PAC requirement based on such a corruption rationale; but his was a lone vote, and in McConnell, there is no reference to the basic corruption rationale (as opposed to the "state-conferred aggregation of corporate wealth" corruption rationale) as supporting the majority's reaffirmation of Austin.)
Marty I too have appreciated your clear analysis of the decision, but i have been baffled by your repeated reference to what we clearly know about the facts of corruption. Let us ignore for the moment the conflicting evidence of political science on this point and chalk it up to the collective weakness of my profession that we cannot prove the obvious, i wonder whether you clearly know that the corrupting connection of soft money through the parties is greater than the corrupting connection that will come through independent expenditures/527s (a central premise of the Court's thinking in Buckley)? Are you predicting that the legislation which has been held up as a result of these corrupting influences will suddenly be unleashed thanks to BCRA? Will even the perception of corruption be lessened? Also if the Court deferred to what is "obviously true" re Congress on soft money, why did it over-ride Congressional judgment in 1973 on the corrupting influence of independent expenditures? Bruce Cain On Fri, 12 Dec 2003, Marty Lederman wrote:Thanks for the detailed and thoughtful response, Bob. 1. On one important issue, perhaps I was less clear than I ought to havebeen: I do not think, for a moment, that in constitutional adjudication, "better 'law' is made when Justices elect among doctrines on the basis of what they view as 'common sense' or 'real-world politics'." I think that, in the case of contribution limitations, the proper doctrine is itself one that is highly deferential to the legislature (call it "O'Brienesque analysis," for short), just as such a doctrine would be more than constitutionally adequate in dealing with a standard-issue statute prohibiting payments to officials. And I don't think that the Court should make that (or any other) doctrinal choice because of common-sense, or real-world politics (my own or the Court's); I simply think that it's the more appropriate First Amendment doctrine to apply to restrictions such as those in BCRA title I, for broader First Amendment reasons that have little to do with campaign-finance questions. Mo! re importantly, it's obvious that the majority of the Court thinks that such a deferential doctrine is appropriate. (As I wrote earlier, I'd be happy to debate whether O'Brienesque/McConnell analysis is correct as a doctrinal matter for contribution limitations; but that's not the topic of this thread.) Once that doctrinal move has been made (and it's my contention that it was made in Buckley itself, and has been applied by the Court ever since in cases of contribution limits), it then is wholly appropriate for the Court to say of the congressional judgment: "Of course that judgment is a reasonable one; indeed, we find it hard to imagine how anyone could reasonably dispute such a common-sense understanding of the effect of money on officeholder conduct.")2. In any event, as I wrote previously, I don't think there's any real debateon the Court (or in the "real" world -- but Bob would know better than I) as to the factual questions on which the Court deferred to Congress's judgment -- the effect of contributions on officeholders' conduct, and the general public perception of that effect. Does Bob contend that there is a real debate on these questions? Does he think that all of the millions of dollars flowing to candidates and parties has no effect on how the law is made and implemented, or that the public does not perceive such an influence? I suspect not. Instead, I think the real debate concerns: (i) whether it is legitimate for Congress to try to stop such influence; (ii) whether alleviating the "perception" of influence is a legitimate congressional concern; and, most importantly, (iii) even if such problems exist, whether they justify a law restricting contribution limitations, a question that turns largely on ho! w much one perceives a serious impingement on party and candidate expression, and on which doctrinal choice one makes for statutes having an incidental impact on speech. In my view, BCRA and McConnell merely take us back to the world that existed in 1977. Was that a world in which campaign speech was unduly inhibited?3. I agree that it would have been better judicial craftwork for the Court toexpressly embrace O'Brien -- or, more precisely, to have never purported to reject O'Brien way back in Buckley itself. But one hardly needs to count up citations to O'Brien to recognize what has been going on: The Court has been plain as day in its recent cases (Beaumont; Shrink Missouri, etc.), and in McConnell it finally abandons all pretense of "exacting scrutiny." I can't imagine the Court being any more "lucid" or "transparent" than it was in McConnell in explaining that there's no "exacting" scrutiny, and that it is applying a highly deferential standard as to contribution limitations.4. As I wrote earlier, I would have liked to see more of a defense of Austin.But I fully understand why the Court "refused to deal seriously with the section 203 issue" -- because it wasn't briefed by the plaintiffs and, more importantly, because SOC obviously was not inclined, without an express invitation and a damn good reason, to overrule a 13-year-old precedent and a 56-year-old practice that corporations and unions were able to live with from 1947 until they started circumventing it in the mid-'90s. Once she understood that the real question here was not the constitutionality of BCRA, but of Taft-Hartley -- no one on the Court is inclined to embrace the express advocacy/issue advocacy distinction; indeed, Kennedy ridicules it -- I imagine that changed her perspective on section 203 quite quickly, as reflected in the opinion.5. Bob writes that "it seems odd to me that one can at once express somedoubt about Congressional motive, as it affects at least203, while championing a decision that enshrines an extreme degree ofdeference to those whose motives have been questioned." Not odd at all if, like me (and the Court), you think that deferential review is appropriate for contribution limitations, but that strict scrutiny is appropriate for expenditure limitations, i.e., for limitations on expression itself.----- Original Message ----- From: "Bauer, Bob-WDC" <RBauer@perkinscoie.com> To: "'Marty Lederman '" <marty.lederman@comcast.net>; "''Rick Hasen ' '"<Rick.Hasen@lls.edu>; <election-law@majordomo.lls.edu>Sent: Friday, December 12, 2003 9:26 AM Subject: RE: McConnell v. FEC: The big pictureA few comments on Marty's post: I cannot help but be troubled by the notion that the Court is deciding a case like this on the basis of a rationale--O'Brien--that it rejected in Buckley but has been applying on an undeclared basis ever since. This is hardly lucid, transparent constitutional decision-making--something like Justice O'Connor's inscrutable position on Austin. This same Court not surprisingly refused to deal seriously with the section 203 issue identified by Marty. For these reasons (and others) the Court's decision strikes me as highly superficial, doctrinally confused and unconvincing. In fact, I am struck by the number of friends who strongly support the statute, who are disappointed with the majority decision's quality. But then again, the Court's performance in this area, both friendly and hostile to Congressional regulation, has been a mess for years. To my mind, this performance also raises issues of democratic self-governance and accountability. I say this without at all believing that the position the Court adopted is unsustainable, but I am reasonably certain that it could have been defended much more effectively. It is absurd to the point of risible for the Court to appeal to "common sense" and the "political realities"--but I agree that these life-time appointees, many of whom have sat on the bench for many decades, concluded that they should adopt the position congruent with their own "common sense" view of electoral politics. I cannot agree with Marty that the better "law" is made when Justices elect among doctrines on the basis of what they view as "common sense" or "real-world politics". This is merely the means by which they breathe their own political preferences into the law--preferences that shape how they interpret the "real world". Moreover, these preferences are dressed up sort of shabbily by appealing to affidavits from individuals who swear under oath, for example, that without soft money, we would have had tort reform, or relying on the solitary judgments of one district court judge on a three-judge panel. I also do not understand how Marty could acknowledge the extreme deferenceto Congress while saying that because the decision was in his view otherwise sound, he doesn't care. This is not an "otherwise" matter: the deference declared by the Court plays a major role in the decision, and also sets up claims we will hear in the future about expansive Congressional authority. (That deference is really the only justification for the Court's otherwise loose treatment of "evidence" supporting the judgment it reached.) Moreover, it seems odd to me that one can at once express some doubt about Congressional motive, as it affects at least 203, while championing a decision that enshrines an extreme degree of deference to those whose motives have been questioned. Finally, I have now often heard and do not agree that the Court's decision flowed from "tactical"errors by the plaintiffs. I also never understood or cared for the emphasis placed on the "federalism" argument. But we shouldall be honest--before a single paper was filed, no-one familiar with the case law doubted that we would see four of the Justices on one side of the case and at least three, probably four, on the other. The plaintiffs did not have all that much room to maneuver: their choices were limited. The same is true also of the defense, to be fair. In the end, the defense carried the day, and did so by catering to the widespread view that "politics is corrupted by soft money and everybody knows it". This was an effective argument, well-supported and nourished by the climate of elite opinion in which the case was heard. In his second round before the Court, I thought that Seth Waxman did an excellent job with this line of argument. -----Original Message----- From: Marty Lederman To: Bauer, Bob-WDC; 'Rick Hasen '; election-law@majordomo.lls.edu Sent: 12/11/2003 7:33 AM Subject: Re: McConnell v. FEC: The big picture Bob and Rick are entirely correct: In its opinion on BCRA title I, the Court is extremely deferential to congressional judgments, and basically embraces numerous findings of one lower-court judge, Judge Koller-Kotelly, without ever discussing whether those findings were adopted by two or more lower-court judges. I, however, am not at all troubled by this, for two reasons: because there's no real dispute on the facts, and because, although there is a very real dispute on the law, I think the majority has the better of the legal argument. As to the facts: The Court's essential "finding" is that elected officials' official conduct is substantially influenced by the money contributed -- to them and to their parties -- by monied interests. Of course that is so. Can anyone sincerely deny it? If money did not bring access and influence, or if access and influence did not affect which laws and regulations are -- and are not -- promulgated, then a whole lot of folks in this town are frittering away a whole lot of time, energy, and money every day. No one actually acts as though money doesn't buy influence, because no one believes it. (And, if that were not enough -- i.e., if anyone really thought that official conduct is not influenced by contributions -- certainly no one could deny that there is a general, quite reasonable perception that this is the case, which, on the Court's view, is reason enough to justify contribution limitations.) The Court felt very comfortable relying upon congressional, and Koller-Kotelly, findings to this effect, because such findings comport so nicely with what the Court correctly views as common sense, and with political life as we know it. The major disputes within the Court are, instead, with respect to two different, legal questions: (i) whether this sort of influence (real or perceived) of money is troubling, or in any event is the sort of thing that Congress can or should legitimately address; and (ii) what the standard of review ought to be. As to the former, there is a very respectable argument, of ancient pedigree, that of course officials' conduct should be -- or will inevitably be -- influenced by the desires of their benefactors, especially (but not exclusively) when the officeholder and the contributor share a basic perspective on policy matters (as is often the case). As Justice Scalia wrote in his dissent, "That is the nature of politics--if not indeed human nature." The majority of the Court disagrees. This is obviously a question worthy of serious debate, but it isn't really a factual question, or a question of appropriate deference. More importantly, there is the question of the appropriate legalstandard. The mistake the Court made in this regard was in Buckley itself, when it nominally -- but not in fact -- rejected O'Brien analysis and insisted that contribution limits be subject to "exacting scrutiny." This holding was honored in the breach right from the outset -- recall the very cursory analysis the Court used in upholding the $25,000 limit in Buckley itself, in a single paragraph on 424 U.S. at 38 -- and it has never been the standard the Court has actually applied. See, most importantly, CalMed. Finally, in Shrink Missouri, Beaumont and McConnell, the Court has conceded that this is so, without ever quite acknowledging expressly that it is, in fact, applying the rather toothless O'Brien standard for restrictions on conduct that have an incidental impact on speech, notwithstanding the fact that it purported to reject O'Brien in Buckley. I happen to think that this is entirely correct as a doctrinal matter. No one, for instance, thinks that a law prohibiting payments to public officials should be subject to "exacting" -- or, indeed, to any -- First Amendment scrutiny, even though such a restriction has an obvious impact on the officials' campaign speech (indeed, even where the payment was intended to subsidize campaign speech). As far as I know, Congress has not treated payments to officials, candidates, parties and PACs differently based on whether such payments are intended (or likely) to be used to pay for expressive activities -- the restrictions apply regardless of the use to which the money is put. For this, among other reasons (e.g., the modest impact on the contributors' speech), I agree that O'Brien scrutiny is appropriate. (This basic argument is, FWIW, the subtext of pages 18-24 of the SG's brief, which I recommend highly.) But, of course, reasonable minds canand do differ, and this is a question even more obviously worthy of very serious debate. The important point for present purposes, however, is that the majority of the Court has rejected the notion of exacting scrutiny. (Justice Scalia is correct in observing that "the 'exacting scrutiny' test of Buckley . . . is not uttered in any majority opinion, and is not observed in the ones from which I dissent.") I think Rick would probably agree that, if there is no "exacting" scrutiny, and if O'Brien applies, then the Court's analysis in title I is quite defensible. If so, then perhaps our attention is better focused on whether and under what circumstances modest O'Brien scrutiny is, in fact, the proper standard for evaluating contribution limitations. Myself, I'm much more troubled by the majority's analysis on section 203. Whatever one thinks of the rationales of Austin, I think it's fair to say that those rationales were not, in fact, what principally prompted Congress to enact section 203. (A much better case can probably be made that they were among the rationales for Congress's initial enactment of the corporate/union PAC requirement in 1947; and I suppose it's fair to say that the current Congress is merely piggybacking on that 56-year-old law. Indeed, I should note that Senators Snowe and Feingold expressly invoked the Austin "corrosive and distorting effects of immense aggregations of wealth that are accumulated with the help of the corporate form" argument in defense of the statute, see 148 Cong. Rec. S2135 (Snowe; 3/20/02), 147 Cong. Rec. S3043 (Snowe; 3/28/01), 147 Cong. Rec. S3072 (Feingold; 3/29/01).). The most powerful part of any plaintiffs' brief, in my view, was the NRA's canvassing of congressional statements explaining that the extension of the PAC requirement was aimed at stopping negative ads. (Scalia quotes many of them at pages 15-16 of his dissent.) I would have liked to see the majority at least address the extent to which such presumably illegitimate objectives, on the part of at least some legislators, should (or should not) affect the Austin analysis. For that matter, it would have been better had the majority actually attempted to defend Austin with more than a single conclusory quotation; but again, that cursory treatment was largely a function of plaintiffs' tactical decision not to challenge the legitimacy of Austin but instead to focus on the very weak alleged distinction between express and issue advocacy, which the Court (again, correctly, in my view) unanimously viewed as a non-issue. ----- Original Message ----- From: "Bauer, Bob-WDC" < <mailto:RBauer@perkinscoie.com> RBauer@perkinscoie.com> To: "'Marty Lederman '" < <mailto:marty.lederman@comcast.net> marty.lederman@comcast.net>; "'Rick Hasen '" < <mailto:Rick.Hasen@lls.edu> Rick.Hasen@lls.edu>; < <mailto:election-law@majordomo.lls.edu> election-law@majordomo.lls.edu> Sent: Wednesday, December 10, 2003 11:55 PM Subject: RE: McConnell v. FEC: The big pictureMarty's thoughtful comments merit more of a considered response than Icanprovide. Also, I suppose I think it poor form to engage too activelyonthese issues so soon after the issuance of the case, when the reform arguments have won the day and skeptics like myself should leaveproponentsto their time of celebration. I will note only that Rick raised, and Marty did not address, thequestionof the deference as the Court handled it. One could not be surprised:I havebeen working for a while now on an article that posits that this isthedirection of the jurisprudence, tentatively titled "When the Pols MaketheCalls". And that is where we are, as the McConnell majority makescontinous,rather relaxed reference to Congress' "expertise" and "superiorknowledge".The expertise is claimed to extend not merely to the "politicalrealities",such as the relation of officeholders to parties, but to the balancingofconstitutional interests in the fashioning of contribution limits.There isnothing approaching cautiousness about motive--partisan,self-interested, orany other kind of motive--nor any obvious room within the Court jurisprudence for serious attentiveness to those kinds of issues. Ifind thediscussion of deference in this opinion to be rather lazy--but theresulthas been headed our way for some time. -----Original Message----- From: Marty LedermanTo: Rick Hasen; <mailto:election-law@majordomo.lls.edu>election-law@majordomo.lls.eduSent: 12/10/2003 6:17 PM Subject: Re: McConnell v. FEC: The big picture I think that, for the most part, the Court did a fine job ofaddressingin sufficient detail the dozens of difficult and contentious issues in the case (although, as noted below, I, too, wonder about some aspectsinwhich its analysis is cursory or cryptic). The majority opinions,afterall, total 146 pages -- far more than I expected, and one of thelongestopinions since M'Culloch. The arguments that got short shriftgenerallywere not the arguments on which the fundamental disputes turned, but were instead among the many diversionary and hypothetical problemsthatthe plaintiffs attempted to place at the heart of the case. For instance, the two examples of holdings cited by Rick are, I think, quite defensible. Yes, the words "promote, support, oppose, or attack " in 323(b) and(f)are somewhat vague. But what's the extent of the potential problem? How often do state and local party committees, and state and local candidates, run ads clearly identifying federal candidates, let alone ads in which it's difficult to ascertain whether the federalcandidatesare being promoted, supported, opposed, or attacked? This will not really be a very serious issue very often -- which is why the partiestothe case devoted very little attention to this vagueness concern in their briefs, and why, if I recall correctly, the dissents do not even address the vagueness concern with respect to those provisions. This does not feel like the stuff of a facial challenge, even if there is some small risk that the vagueness concern will arise in some unforseeable case in the future.What about "electioneering communications" (under teh primary definition) that are not, in fact, intended to influence the outcomeofa federal election? Well, I had thought -- based largely on Rick's excellent brief -- that even this should not be a problem, for either the application of the disclosure provision (201), or for the PAC requirement (203), because the rationales that support suchrequirementsas to express advocacy (e.g., Austin as to 203; Buckley as to 201)applywith full force to such "issue ads," regardless of the speaker'sintent.The Court, however, actually leaves open the possibility that section 203 would be constitutionally questionable as applied to an ad that is actually not intended to influence federal elections. So, Rick asks, why didn't the Court do more to explain why the possibility of such as-applied problems does not render section 203 facially overbroad?Onelikely answer: Because, as was apparent at oral argument, no Justiceonthe Court truly believes that an appreciable number of ads covered by the primary definition are not, in fact, intended to influence federal elections. Indeed, Kennedy's dissent goes to great length (pp. 44-45) -- as did, e.g., the AFL-CIO brief -- to demonstrate that of course issue ads covered by the definition are, at least in part, intended to influence federal elections. Certainly, the majority thinks there'snoreal argument about this: "the vast majority of ads clearly had suchapurpose," slip op. at 100, which was made especially clear by the fact that ads meeting the definition are virtually unheard of except in the run-up to a federal election. The notion of an electioneering communication that is not intended to influence a federal election isamere abstraction, or remote possibility, the majority concludes: noonehas actually ever seen such an animal. There's a good reason Kennedy does not even engage on the "substantial overbreadth" argument to which the Court, in Rick's view, gave short shrift: because the real battle on the Court is not as to the magic words, or Broadrick, but instead over whether Austin was correctly decided. (And as to section 201, there's no real battle at all --eightJustices are ok with basic disclosure provisions on electioneering communications -- just as Rick urged.) Much ink was spilled, inacademeand in the lower courts, over magic words and substantial overbreadth--but that was always a red herring, based on the Court's sloppy use of the term "overbreadth" in Buckley and in MCFL. By the time the case reached the Supreme Court, the issue wasn't that at all, but wasinsteadwhether there were still five votes for Austin. The entirety of the Court appears to agree that if Austin is correct, then section 203 is constitutional, and I think everyone would agree that if Austin were overruled, section 203 would fall. The failure of the plaintiffshere,in my humble opinion, was to fixate on magic words, and to pretend as though Austin was never decided, and did not present much of aproblem.(Austin was barely mentioned in their opening briefs.) Austin was, by contrast, the be-all-and-end-all of the defendants' argument onsection203. It's not for nothing that, after Paul Clement expressly invoked Austin for the eighteenth time in his oral argument, Scaliainterjectedand asked "You really like Austin, don't you?," to which Clement replied, emphatically, "I love Austin. It's binding precedent. [A]smuchas the plaintiffs don't seem to like the case, I don't really hearthemasking this Court to overrule it." In retrospect, that was the case, right there. (That, and/or the following exchange: JUSTICE SCALIA: "[Austin was] [f]ive to four and don't blame it on me." (Laughter.) MR. CLEMENT: "Very well, Justice Scalia, but I'll take the five tofour.And many of the arguments that are being raised in opposition to this statute are the arguments of the dissenters in Austin, not theargumentsof the majority opinion in Austin. And I think that's an important point." No doubt Clement's principal audience for these remarks wastheChief; but obviously, they had some impact on O'Connor.) Which leads me to my own two examples where I think the Court'sopinionis somewhat cryptic: First, although Kennedy goes on for pages about why Austin was wronglydecided, the Court barely says anything about why it was rightlydecided-- basically just a single quotation at the top of page 99 about the distorting effects caused by advantages of the corporate form. O'Connor's basic tactic here, I think, was simply to say that once the plaintiffs had, in effect, conceded the rightness of Austin, there was no real ground for not extending it here. My sense is that, even ifshedoes not believe Austin was correctly decided, she does not think it's appropriate for the Court to overturn a 56-year-old regime, thirteen years after the Court upheld that very regime by a 6-3 vote -- especially in a case where no one was asking for an overruling. (The failure of the Court to engage the AFL-CIO's argument that Austin does not and should not apply to unions can probably be chalked up to the fact that this argument was, to say the least, a muted theme in theAFLbriefs and argument, see oral argument at 140-41 -- and to the factthatit's virtually inconceivable the Court would uphold the PACrequirementas to corporations but not as to unions.) My second example is that, in upholding the various differentdisclosureprovisions, the Court acts as though McIntyre doesn't even exist. Itisvery difficult to reconcile all of the Court's disclosure/anonymity precedents -- e.g., Talley; Buckey v. Valeo; Buckley v. ACLF;McIntyre;Watchtower; Harriss; the Riley line of cases; etc. The Court did not even try to do so here. But again, this is largely because of a questionable tactic by the plaintiffs: They did not really engage on the disclosure provisions at all, and barely mentioned McIntyre intheirbriefs. (There's a passing reference in the ACLU brief and more extensive discussion in Ron Paul's brief.) Indeed, at oral argument(pp. 130-132), Floyd Abrams even more or less conceded the constitutionality of the disclosure provisions (while noting theACLU'sobjections). Having said all that, I should add that, at least as to contribution limitations, it may be fair to see this as Rick does, as theculminationof a seismic shift. Myself, though, I think that the Court is only recently (e.g., in Shrink Missouri and Beaumont) acknowledging in its rhetoric what it had in fact been doing all along in the area of poltical contributions, i.e., exchanges of money -- namely, nottreatingcontributions as anywhere close to analogous to speech itself.Today'sdecision on title I, along with Shrink Missouri and Beaumont, flowsverynaturally -- one might even say inevitably -- from the Court'sdecisionsupholding the $25,000 limit in Buckley (which was, in essence, a restriction on what we now think of as "soft money" contributions to parties), and upholding the $5000 limit on contributions to PACs in CalMed. ----- Original Message ----- From: Rick Hasen < <mailto:Rick.Hasen@lls.edu>mailto:Rick.Hasen@lls.edu>To: election-law < <mailto:election-law@majordomo.lls.edu>mailto:election-law@majordomo.lls.edu>Sent: Wednesday, December 10, 2003 6:52 PM Subject: McConnell v. FEC: The big picture McConnell v. FEC: The Big Picture Although today's opinion is significant on the doctrinal questions of soft money and issue advocacy, I want to step back for a minute andlookat the big picture, and to me the big picture is the Court's cursory dismissal of First Amendment arguments. I write these words as a supporter of the Court's determination that the soft money and issueadvocacy provisions are constitutional. My complaint is that the Court reached the decision too easily. Consider two prominent examples, that I describe in more detail in the post below. First, the majority dismissed in a single paragraph a concern that the new issue advertisement provision would violate the First Amendment by regulating too much speech not intended toinfluencethe outcome of elections. The three-judge court that had consideredtheissue before the Supreme Court devoted hundreds of pages to the questions of substantial overbreadth---in my view a close anddifficultquestion. Second, the majority dismissed in a footnote the vagueness attack onthepromote, support, oppose, or attack definition of federal election activity. Perhaps the Court really has confidence that the FEC cancraftsome workable regulations here, but the recent history of the FECgivesme little confidence. The Court's cursory dismissal of the First Amendment concernillustrateswhat is most stunning about the opinion: its willingness to defer to Congress over the appropriate role of money in politics. Buckley maynotquite be dead yet, but the opinion marks the completion of a seismic shift begun by the Court in 2000 away from Buckley and toward a more holistic view of the democratic process and the proper role of moneyinpolitics. Thus, McConnell v. FEC follows the Court's decision in 2000 in Shrink Missouri to uphold Missouri's very low contribution limits forstatewideoffice, its decision in Colorado Republican II in 2001 to upholdlimitson party spending coordinated with candidates, and its opinion in Beaumont last June upholding Congressional limits on non-profit corporate electoral activity.These opinions never explicitly overrule Buckley. But rather thanfocus,as Buckley did, solely on a First Amendment interest that debate be "uninhibited, robust, and wide-open," the new opinions see, in thewordsof Justice Breyer concurring in the 2000 case, "constitutionally protected interests on both sides of the legal equation." Brad Smith made similar points about Buckley's loss of vitality after Beaumont. Bradley Smith, "Campaign Finance Reform: Searching for Corruption in All the Wrong Places," 2002-2003 Cato Supreme CourtReview187. Now I don't agree with Brad Smith on whether the demise of Buckley isagood thing or not. But I think the Court should have given morecarefultreatment to some of the First Amendment concerns. If not, the dangeristhat self-interested legislation makes its way through very easilyunderthe guise of campaign finance reform. (I know some people put BCRA itself into this category---for the most part (excepting things liketheMillionaire's Provision), I don't). -- Rick Hasen Professor of Law and William M. Rains Fellow Loyola Law School 919 South Albany Street Los Angeles, CA 90015-1211 (213)736-1466 (213)380-3769 - fax <mailto:rick.hasen@lls.edu> rick.hasen@lls.edu <<mailto:rick.hasen@lls.edu> mailto:rick.hasen@lls.edu><http://www.lls.edu/academics/faculty/hasen.html>http://www.lls.edu/academics/faculty/hasen.html< <http://www.lls.edu/academics/faculty/hasen.html>http://www.lls.edu/academics/faculty/hasen.html><http://electionlawblog.org> http://electionlawblog.org <<http://electionlawblog.org> http://electionlawblog.org>